Wage slavery: Difference between revisions

From ProleWiki, the proletarian encyclopedia
No edit summary
Line 76: Line 76:


==Opinions on psychological effects==
==Opinions on psychological effects==
[[Image:WilhelmvonHumboldt.jpg|thumb|right|290px|[[Wilhelm von Humboldt]]]]
Investigative journalist [[Robert Kuttner]] in ''Everything for Sale'', analyzes the work of public-Health scholars Jeffrey Johnson and Ellen Hall about modern conditions of work, and concludes that "to be in a life situation where one experiences relentless demands by others, over which one has relatively little control, is to be at risk of poor health, physically as well as mentally." Under wage labor, "a relatively small elite demands and gets empowerment, self-actualization, autonomy, and other work satisfaction that partially compensate for long hours" while "epidemiological data confirm that lower-paid, lower-status workers are more likely to experience the most clinically damaging forms of stress, in part because they have less control over their work."<ref>Kuttner, ''Op. Cit.'', p. 153 and p. 154</ref>


Analysis of the psychological implications of wage slavery goes back to the [[Age of Enlightenment|Enlightenment]] era. In his 1791 book On the Limits of State Action, classical liberal thinker Wilhelm von Humboldt explained how "whatever does not spring from a man's free choice, or is only the result of instruction and guidance, does not enter into his very nature; he does not perform it with truly human energies, but merely with mechanical exactness"— and so when the laborer works under external control, "we may admire what he does, but we despise what he is."<ref>[http://books.zcommunications.org/chomsky/year/year-c01-s06.html Year 501: Chapter One [6/12&amp;#93;<!--Bot-generated title-->]</ref>
Wage slavery, and the educational system that precedes it "implies power held by the leader. Without power the leader is inept. The possession of power inevitably leads to corruption… in spite of… good intentions … [Leadership means] power of initiative, this sense of responsibility, the self-respect which comes from expressed manhood, is taken from the men, and consolidated in the leader. The sum of their initiative, their responsibility, their self-respect becomes his … [and the] order and system he maintains is based upon the suppression of the men, from being independent thinkers into being 'the men' … In a word, he is compelled to become an autocrat and a foe to democracy." For the "leader", such marginalisation can be beneficial, for a leader "sees no need for any high level of intelligence in the rank and file, except to applaud his actions. Indeed such intelligence from his point of view, by breeding criticism and opposition, is an obstacle and causes confusion."<ref>''The Miners' Next Step'', pp. 16-17 and p. 15</ref> Wage slavery "implies erosion of the human personality… [because] some men submit to the will of others, arousing in these instincts which predispose them to cruelty and indifference in the face of the suffering of their fellows."<ref>quoted by Jose Peirats, ''The CNT in the Spanish Revolution'', vol. 2, p. 76</ref>
 
Investigative journalist [[Robert Kuttner]] in ''Everything for Sale'', analyzes the work of public-Health scholars Jeffrey Johnson and Ellen Hall about modern conditions of work, and concludes that "''to be in a life situation where one experiences relentless demands by others, over which one has relatively little control, is to be at risk of poor health, physically as well as mentally.''" Under wage labor, "''a relatively small elite demands and gets empowerment, self-actualization, autonomy, and other work satisfaction that partially compensate for long hours''" while "''epidemiological data confirm that lower-paid, lower-status workers are more likely to experience the most clinically damaging forms of stress, in part because they have less control over their work.''"<ref>Kuttner, ''Op. Cit.'', p. 153 and p. 154</ref>
 
Wage slavery, and the educational system that precedes it "''implies power held by the leader. Without power the leader is inept. The possession of power inevitably leads to corruption… in spite of… good intentions … [Leadership means] power of initiative, this sense of responsibility, the self-respect which comes from expressed manhood, is taken from the men, and consolidated in the leader. The sum of their initiative, their responsibility, their self-respect becomes his … [and the] order and system he maintains is based upon the suppression of the men, from being independent thinkers into being 'the men' … In a word, he is compelled to become an autocrat and a foe to democracy.''" For the "leader", such marginalisation can be beneficial, for a leader "''sees no need for any high level of intelligence in the rank and file, except to applaud his actions. Indeed such intelligence from his point of view, by breeding criticism and opposition, is an obstacle and causes confusion.''"<ref>''The Miners' Next Step'', pp. 16-17 and p. 15</ref> Wage slavery "''implies erosion of the human personality… [because] some men submit to the will of others, arousing in these instincts which predispose them to cruelty and indifference in the face of the suffering of their fellows.''"<ref>quoted by Jose Peirats, ''The CNT in the Spanish Revolution'', vol. 2, p. 76</ref>


[[Erich Fromm]] noted that if a person perceives himself as being what he owns, then when that person loses (or even thinks of losing) what he "owns" (e.g. the good looks or sharp mind that allow him to sell his labor for high wages), then, a fear of loss may create anxiety and authoritarian tendencies because that person's sense of identity is threatened. In contrast, when a person's sense of self is based on what he experiences in a state of ''being'' (creativity, ego or loss of ego, love, sadness, taste, sight etc.) with a less materialistic regard for what he once had and lost, or may lose, then less authoritarian tendencies prevail. The state of being, in his view, flourishes under a worker-managed workplace and economy, whereas self-ownership entails a materialistic notion of self, created to rationalize the lack of worker control that would allow for a state of being.<ref>[http://books.google.com/books?id=JvG85s966koC&amp;dq=to+have+or+to+be&amp;printsec=frontcover&amp;source=bn&amp;hl=en&amp;ei=AbpnS7-aGJyysQOe0fjVBA&amp;sa=X&amp;oi=book_result&amp;ct=result&amp;resnum=5&amp;ved=0CCMQ6AEwBA#v=onepage&amp;q=&amp;f=false To Have Or to Be? by Erich Fromm ]</ref>
[[Erich Fromm]] noted that if a person perceives himself as being what he owns, then when that person loses (or even thinks of losing) what he "owns" (e.g. the good looks or sharp mind that allow him to sell his labor for high wages), then, a fear of loss may create anxiety and authoritarian tendencies because that person's sense of identity is threatened. In contrast, when a person's sense of self is based on what he experiences in a state of ''being'' (creativity, ego or loss of ego, love, sadness, taste, sight etc.) with a less materialistic regard for what he once had and lost, or may lose, then less authoritarian tendencies prevail. The state of being, in his view, flourishes under a worker-managed workplace and economy, whereas self-ownership entails a materialistic notion of self, created to rationalize the lack of worker control that would allow for a state of being.<ref>[http://books.google.com/books?id=JvG85s966koC&amp;dq=to+have+or+to+be&amp;printsec=frontcover&amp;source=bn&amp;hl=en&amp;ei=AbpnS7-aGJyysQOe0fjVBA&amp;sa=X&amp;oi=book_result&amp;ct=result&amp;resnum=5&amp;ved=0CCMQ6AEwBA#v=onepage&amp;q=&amp;f=false To Have Or to Be? by Erich Fromm ]</ref>
Line 103: Line 99:


==Worker cooperatives, syndicalism and self-management==
==Worker cooperatives, syndicalism and self-management==
Some social activists objecting to the [[market system]] or [[price system]] of wage working, historically have considered [[syndicalism]], [[worker cooperative]]s, [[workers' self-management]] and [[workers' control]] as possible alternatives to the current wage system.<ref name="globetrotter.berkeley.edu" /><ref name="socialissues.wiseto.com"/><ref name="spunk.org"/><ref name="Geoffrey Ostergaard p. 133"/>


===Labor and government===
The American philosopher [[John Dewey]] believed that until "industrial feudalism" is replaced by "industrial democracy," politics will be "the shadow cast on society by big business". [[Thomas Ferguson (academic)|Thomas Ferguson]] has postulated in his [[investment theory of party competition]] that the undemocratic nature of economic institutions under capitalism causes elections to become occasions when blocs of investors coalesce and compete to control the state.<ref>[http://books.google.com/books?id=CU8oyIlNyQcC&amp;dq=investment+theory+party+competition&amp;printsec=frontcover&amp;source=bl&amp;ots=qilco5PlJF&amp;sig=NknYgcSaZF0OQ2ilcwDuz6kJssM&amp;hl=en&amp;ei=_8uYSvTDDof-tQOZx92pAg&amp;sa=X&amp;oi=book_result&amp;ct=result&amp;resnum=4#v=onepage&amp;q=&amp;f=false Thomas Ferguson, Golden rule: the investment theory of party competition and the logic of money-driven political systems]</ref>


[[Image:Noam chomsky cropped.jpg|thumb|left|Noam Chomsky]]
[[Image:Noam chomsky cropped.jpg|thumb|left|Noam Chomsky]]


[[Noam Chomsky]] has argued that political theory tends to blur the 'elite' function of government:<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://www.chomsky.info/interviews/19760725.htm |title=Interview |publisher=Chomsky}}</ref>
[[Noam Chomsky]] has said that<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://www.chomsky.info/interviews/19760725.htm |title=Interview |publisher=Chomsky}}</ref>
 
{{Quote|As long as individuals are compelled to rent themselves on the market to those who are willing to hire them, as long as their role in production is simply that of ancillary tools, then there are striking elements of coercion and oppression that make talk of democracy very limited, if even meaningful…}}
''“Modern political theory stresses Madison's belief that "in a just and a free government the rights both of property and of persons ought to be effectually guarded." But in this case too it is useful to look at the doctrine more carefully. There are no rights of property, only rights to property that is, rights of persons with property,...<ref>[http://www.thirdworldtraveler.com/Chomsky/ConsentPOP_Chom.html Consent Without Consent Profit Over People Noam Chomsky]</ref> ""[In] [r]epresentative democracy, as in, say, the United States or Great Britain… there is a monopoly of power centralized in the state, and secondly– and critically– […] the representative democracy is limited to the political sphere and in no serious way encroaches on the economic sphere... 'That is, as long as individuals are compelled to rent themselves on the market to those who are willing to hire them, as long as their role in production is simply that of ancillary tools, then there are striking elements of coercion and oppression that make talk of democracy very limited, if even meaningful…”''


In this regard Chomsky has used [[Bakunin]]'s theories about an "instinct for freedom",<ref name = "Chomsky">{{Cite web|url=http://www.chomsky.info/interviews/20070921.htm |title=Interview |author=CHOMSKY, Noam |date=2007-09-21}}</ref> the militant history of labor movements, [[Kropotkin]]'s mutual aid evolutionary principle of survival and [[Marc Hauser]]'s theories supporting an innate and universal moral faculty,<ref>Moral Minds: How Nature Designed Our Universal Sense of Right and Wrong by Marc Hauser</ref> to explain the incompatibility of oppression with certain aspects of human nature.<ref>[http://video.google.com/videoplay?docid=-3740467851698161135 On Just War Theory at West Point Academy: Hauser's theories "could some day provide foundations for a more substantive theory of just war," expanding on some of the existing legal "codifications of these intuitive judgments" that are regularly disregarded by elite power structures. (min 26-30)]</ref><ref name = "Chomsky 2004">{{Cite web|url=http://www.chomsky.info/interviews/20040714.htm |title=Interview |author=CHOMSKY, Noam |date=2004-07-14}}</ref>
In this regard Chomsky has used [[Bakunin]]'s theories about an "instinct for freedom",<ref name = "Chomsky">{{Cite web|url=http://www.chomsky.info/interviews/20070921.htm |title=Interview |author=CHOMSKY, Noam |date=2007-09-21}}</ref> the militant history of labor movements, [[Kropotkin]]'s mutual aid evolutionary principle of survival and [[Marc Hauser]]'s theories supporting an innate and universal moral faculty,<ref>Moral Minds: How Nature Designed Our Universal Sense of Right and Wrong by Marc Hauser</ref> to explain the incompatibility of oppression with certain aspects of human nature.<ref>[http://video.google.com/videoplay?docid=-3740467851698161135 On Just War Theory at West Point Academy: Hauser's theories "could some day provide foundations for a more substantive theory of just war," expanding on some of the existing legal "codifications of these intuitive judgments" that are regularly disregarded by elite power structures. (min 26-30)]</ref><ref name = "Chomsky 2004">{{Cite web|url=http://www.chomsky.info/interviews/20040714.htm |title=Interview |author=CHOMSKY, Noam |date=2004-07-14}}</ref>

Revision as of 03:51, 12 May 2022

Wage slavery is a term for wage labour which emphasises the unfree aspects of that labour. "Wage slavery" and similar terms have been in frequent use almost as long as capitalist wage labour has existed. For example, in 1818 an English cotton worker described the cotton manufacturers as "despotic" masters who ruled over the "English Spinner slave."[1] This worker also employed an analysis later used by Karl Marx and others, that the wage woker is unfree because he cannot escape the necessity of working for some capitalist master in order to survive:

It is vain to insult our common understandings with the observation that such men are free; that the law protects the rich and poor alike, and that a spinner can leave his master if he does not like the wages. True; so he can; but where must he go? why to another to be sure.

— English cotton worker, 1818


By the time Marx had entered university, similar ideas were current in Germany. Marx's law lecturer, Eduard Gans wrote in 1836 that a visit to the English factories showed that "slavery is not yet over, that it has been formally abolished, but materially is completely in existence."[2]

Marx used the idea at least as early as in his Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844, in which he wrote that workers are forced to "carry out slave-labour, completely giving up their freedom, in the service of greed."[3]

In 1847 Marx noted, as others had before, that the slave had some advantage over the wage worker in being more valuable to the master or less easily replaced:

The slave is sold once and for all; the proletarian must sell himself daily and hourly. The individual slave, property of one master, is assured an existence, however miserable it may be, because of the master's interest. The individual proletarian, property as it were of the entire bourgeois class which buys his labor only when someone has need of it, has no secure existence.

— Karl Marx, The Principles of Communism 1847


In "Wage Labour and Capital" (1849), he wrote that "the relation of wage labour to capital, [is] the slavery of the worker, the domination of the capitalist."[4]

Marx argued that although the wage labourer is not owned by any particular capitalist she or he is, in effect, owned by the capitalist class. In "Wage-Labour and Capital" he wrote that because the worker's "sole source of livelihood is the sale of his labour, [he] cannot leave the whole class of purchasers, that is, the capitalist class, without renouncing his existence. He belongs not to this or that bourgeois, but to the bourgeosie, the bourgeois class."[5]

In Das Kapital (1867) Marx even says that because of this structural domination over the worker,

the worker belongs to capital before he has sold himself to the capitalist.

Marx Engels Collected Works, volume 35, p. 577.


In Theories of Surplus Value (1861-63), Marx noted that the French writer Simon Linquet had made the necessity argument already in 1767:[6]

The slave was precious to his master because of the money he had cost him… They were worth at least as much as they could be sold for in the market… It is the impossibility of living by any other means that compels our farm labourers to till the soil whose fruits they will not eat… It is want that compels them to go down on their knees to the rich man in order to get from him permission to enrich him… what effective gain [has] the suppression of slavery brought [him ?] He is free, you say. Ah! That is his misfortune… These men… [have] the most terrible, the most imperious of masters, that is, need. … They must therefore find someone to hire them, or die of hunger. Is that to be free?

— Simon Linguet, Théorie des lois civiles, etc., p. 467.



In The Making of the English Working Class, (1963) Marxist historian E.P. Thompson argued that the working-class' complaint during the 19th century industrial revolution in England was not reducible to a decline in material well-being. What mattered to workers was how the conditions of their work had changed - that their working life was now characterized by overwork, monotony, discipline, and most importantly the loss of freedom and independence. Thompson thus observed that 'People may consume more goods and become less happy or less free at the same time.'[7]


Use or misuse in defence of actual slavery

Before the American Civil War, Southern defenders of African American slavery invoked the concept of wage slavery to favorably compare the condition of their slaves to workers in the North.[8][9] Some argued that workers were "free but in name – the slaves of endless toil," and that their slaves were better off.[10] This contention has been partly corroborated by some modern studies. According to historians Fogel and Engerman plantation records show that slaves worked less, were better fed and whipped only occasionally—their material conditions in the 19th century being "better than what was typically available to free urban laborers at the time".[11] According to another study, slaves in the United States in the 19th century had improved their standard of living from the 18th century.[12] According to Mark Michael Smith of the Economic History Society, slaves could sometimes manipulate the master-slave relationship enough to "carve out a degree of autonomy"[13]

Many abolitionists in the U.S., including northern capitalists, regarded the notion of wage slavery to be spurious,[14] saying that wage workers were "neither wronged nor oppressed".[15]

The abolitionist and former slave Frederick Douglass declared "Now I am my own master" when he took a paying job.[16]

Abraham Lincoln and the republicans "did not challenge the notion that those who spend their entire lives as wage laborers were comparable to slaves", though they argued that the condition was different, as laborers were likely to have the opportunity to work for themselves in the future, achieving self-employment.[17]

History

The imagery of wage slavery was widely used by labor organizations during the mid-19th century to object to the lack of workers' self-management. However, it was gradually replaced by the more pragmatic term "wage work" towards the end of the 19th century, as labor organizations shifted their focus to raising wages.[18][19]

Henry David Thoreau wrote that “[i]t is hard to have a Southern overseer; it is worse to have a Northern one; but worst of all when you are the slave-driver of yourself.” [20]

In the United States, self-employment became less common as the artisan tradition slowly disappeared in the later part of the 19th century. In 1869 The New York Times described the system of wage labor as "a system of slavery as absolute if not as degrading as that which lately prevailed at the South".[17]

E. P. Thompson notes that for British workers at the end of the 18th and beginning of the 19th centuries, the "gap in status between a 'servant,' a hired wage-laborer subject to the orders and discipline of the master, and an artisan, who might 'come and go' as he pleased, was wide enough for men to shed blood rather than allow themselves to be pushed from one side to the other. And, in the value system of the community, those who resisted degradation were in the right." [21] A "Member of the Builders' Union" in the 1830s argued that the trade unions "will not only strike for less work, and more wages, but will ultimately abolish wages, become their own masters and work for each other; labor and capital will no longer be separate but will be indissolubly joined together in the hands of workmen and work-women."[22] This perspective inspired the Grand National Consolidated Trades Union of 1834 which had the "two-fold purpose of syndicalist unions – the protection of the workers under the existing system and the formation of the nuclei of the future society" when the unions "take over the whole industry of the country." [23] "Research has shown", summarises William Lazonick, "that the 'free-born Englishman' of the eighteenth century – even those who, by force of circumstance, had to submit to agricultural wage labour – tenaciously resisted entry into the capitalist workshop."[24]


Historically, the range of occupations and status positions held by chattel slaves has been nearly as broad as that held by free persons, indicating some similarities between chattel slavery and wage slavery as well.[25]


In the 1830s the Lowell Mill Girls condemned the "degradation and subordination" of the newly emerging industrial system[26][27] and expressed their concerns in a protest song during their 1836 strike:

Oh! isn't it a pity, such a pretty girl as I
Should be sent to the factory to pine away and die?
Oh! I cannot be a slave, I will not be a slave,
For I'm so fond of liberty,
That I cannot be a slave.[28]
Emma Goldman famously denounced wage slavery by saying: "The only difference is that you are hired slaves instead of block slaves"[29]

According to Helga Hallgrimsdottir the term "wage slavery" was widely used by labor organizations during the mid-19th century, but was gradually replaced by the term "wage work" towards the end of the 19th century.[30]


Anthropologist David Graeber has noted that, historically, the first wage labor contracts we know about—whether in ancient Greece or Rome, or in the Malay or Swahili city states in the Indian ocean—were in fact contracts for the rental of chattel slaves (usually the owner would receive a share of the money, and the slave, another, with which to maintain his or her living expenses.) Such arrangements were quite common in New World slavery as well, whether in the United States or Brazil. C. L. R. James made a famous argument that most of the techniques of human organization employed on factory workers during the industrial revolution were first developed on slave plantations.[31]

Opinions on psychological effects

Investigative journalist Robert Kuttner in Everything for Sale, analyzes the work of public-Health scholars Jeffrey Johnson and Ellen Hall about modern conditions of work, and concludes that "to be in a life situation where one experiences relentless demands by others, over which one has relatively little control, is to be at risk of poor health, physically as well as mentally." Under wage labor, "a relatively small elite demands and gets empowerment, self-actualization, autonomy, and other work satisfaction that partially compensate for long hours" while "epidemiological data confirm that lower-paid, lower-status workers are more likely to experience the most clinically damaging forms of stress, in part because they have less control over their work."[32]

Wage slavery, and the educational system that precedes it "implies power held by the leader. Without power the leader is inept. The possession of power inevitably leads to corruption… in spite of… good intentions … [Leadership means] power of initiative, this sense of responsibility, the self-respect which comes from expressed manhood, is taken from the men, and consolidated in the leader. The sum of their initiative, their responsibility, their self-respect becomes his … [and the] order and system he maintains is based upon the suppression of the men, from being independent thinkers into being 'the men' … In a word, he is compelled to become an autocrat and a foe to democracy." For the "leader", such marginalisation can be beneficial, for a leader "sees no need for any high level of intelligence in the rank and file, except to applaud his actions. Indeed such intelligence from his point of view, by breeding criticism and opposition, is an obstacle and causes confusion."[33] Wage slavery "implies erosion of the human personality… [because] some men submit to the will of others, arousing in these instincts which predispose them to cruelty and indifference in the face of the suffering of their fellows."[34]

Erich Fromm noted that if a person perceives himself as being what he owns, then when that person loses (or even thinks of losing) what he "owns" (e.g. the good looks or sharp mind that allow him to sell his labor for high wages), then, a fear of loss may create anxiety and authoritarian tendencies because that person's sense of identity is threatened. In contrast, when a person's sense of self is based on what he experiences in a state of being (creativity, ego or loss of ego, love, sadness, taste, sight etc.) with a less materialistic regard for what he once had and lost, or may lose, then less authoritarian tendencies prevail. The state of being, in his view, flourishes under a worker-managed workplace and economy, whereas self-ownership entails a materialistic notion of self, created to rationalize the lack of worker control that would allow for a state of being.[35]

Due to this lack of control, the exploited worker, according to Marx, "puts his life into the object... [and thus] the greater his activity...the less he possesses...[H]is labour becomes an object...[and] the life which he has given to the object sets itself against him as an alien and hostile force"[36] And since the worker could be working for wages or saving money instead of enjoying life or having fun, (which in a capitalist society often costs money), "all passions and all activity is submerged in avarice...[and] the less you are, the less you express your own life, the more you have, i.e., the greater is your alienated life."[37]

Both the Milgram and Stanford experiments have been found useful in the psychological study of wage-based workplace relations.[38]

Methods of control in wage systems

In 19th century discussions of labor relations, it was normally assumed that the threat of starvation forced those without property to work for wages. Proponents of the view that modern forms of employment constitute wage slavery, even when workers appear to have a range of available alternatives, have attributed its perpetuation to a variety of social factors that maintain the hegemony of the employer class.[39][40] These include efforts at Manufacturing Consent and eliciting false consciousness.

In the 21st century Dubai, employers pay low wages to many workers—often less than £120 ($178.83) a month, for a 60-hour work week. Often 'employment contracts', if they are given, "are not worth the paper they are written on," and collective bargaining and trade unions are illegal in Dubai. It all starts in their home countries, often India or Bangladesh, where local recruitment agents promise them high salaries and generous overtime payments. In these workers' home countries they are charged a "visa" or "transit" fee, averaging 200,000 taka, or £2,000 ($2,980), which in these home countries is supposed to be illegal.

The workers pay the fee because they believe the figures they've been promised of future wages. However in most cases, it will take them the entire two-to-three year contract for them just to pay back that fee and break even.[41]

In another contemporary case unions representing teachers in Louisiana have filed a complaint with state authorities alleging that a Los Angeles recruiting firm broke the law by holding more than 350 Filipino teachers in 'virtual servitude' in order to hold onto their jobs in five Louisiana parish school systems, including New Orleans' Recovery School District.[42]

In his book, Disciplined Minds, Jeff Schmidt points out that professionals are trusted to run organizations in the interests of their employers. Because employers cannot be on hand to manage every decision, professionals are trained to “ensure that each and every detail of their work favors the right interests–or skewers the disfavored ones” in the absence of overt control:

The resulting professional is an obedient thinker, an intellectual property whom employers can trust to experiment, theorize, innovate and create safely within the confines of an assigned ideology.[43]


Worker cooperatives, syndicalism and self-management

File:Noam chomsky cropped.jpg
Noam Chomsky

Noam Chomsky has said that[44]

As long as individuals are compelled to rent themselves on the market to those who are willing to hire them, as long as their role in production is simply that of ancillary tools, then there are striking elements of coercion and oppression that make talk of democracy very limited, if even meaningful…


In this regard Chomsky has used Bakunin's theories about an "instinct for freedom",[45] the militant history of labor movements, Kropotkin's mutual aid evolutionary principle of survival and Marc Hauser's theories supporting an innate and universal moral faculty,[46] to explain the incompatibility of oppression with certain aspects of human nature.[47][48]

Influence on environmental degradation

Loyola University philosophy professor John Clark and libertarian socialist philosopher Murray Bookchin have criticized the system of wage labor for encouraging environmental destruction, arguing that a self-managed industrial society would better manage the environment. They, like other anarchists,[49] attribute much of the industrial revolution's pollution to the "hierarchical" and "competitive" economic relations accompanying it.[50][51][52][53][54]

Criticism

According to Eric Foner, most abolitionists in the U.S. regarded the analogy of wage earners to slaves, symbolized by the term "wage slavery," as spurious. Abolitionist William Lloyd Garrison stated that the use of the term "wage slavery" (in a time when chattel slavery was still common) was an "abuse of language."[14] Most abolitionists believed that wage workers were "neither wronged nor oppressed".[15] Former slave and abolitionist Frederick Douglass described his elation when he took a paying job, declaring that "Now I am my own master." According to Douglass, wage labor did not represent oppression but fair exchange and former slaves for the first time receiving the fruits of their labor.[16]

Philosopher Gary Young has argued that the same basic reasoning that considers the individual to be forced to sell his labor to a capitalist in order to survive, also applies to the capitalist in that he is forced to hire a worker to survive otherwise his capital will be exhausted through consumption, leaving him nothing to purchase the necessities of life.[55] In this sense, the capitalists depend on the workers as the workers depend on the capitalists.[56]

In mainstream economic philosophy, wage labor is seen as the voluntary sale of one's own time and efforts, just like a carpenter would sell a chair, or a farmer would sell wheat. It is considered neither an antagonistic nor abusive relationship, and carries no particular moral implications. From this perspective, the problem of poverty comes from an unequal distribution of income and can be addressed by government programs like social security and progressive taxation, and does not reflect a fundamental flaw in the capitalist system.[57]

Wage slavery is also in contradiction to the classical liberal notion of self-ownership. Under this view, a person is not free unless he can sell himself, because if a person does not own themself, they must be owned by either another individual or a group of individuals. The ability for anyone to consent to an activity or action would then be placed in the hands of a third party. Further, the third-party's ownership would also be in the hands of yet another individual or group. This regression of ownership would transfer ad infinitum and leave no one with the ability to coordinate their own actions or those of anyone else. The conclusion is therefore that if under wage slavery, self-ownership is not legitimate, there is no right for anyone then to claim enslavement to wages in the first place.[58] Of course, wage slavery can be seen as a form of duress, in that one must be a wage slave to survive.

Employment contracts

Some criticize wage slavery on strictly contractual grounds, e.g. David Ellerman and Carole Pateman, arguing that the employment contract is a legal fiction in that it treats human beings juridically as mere tools or inputs by abdicating responsibility and self-determination, which the critics argue are inalienable. As Ellerman points out, "[t]he employee is legally transformed from being a co-responsible partner to being only an input supplier sharing no legal responsibility for either the input liabilities [costs] or the produced outputs [revenue, profits] of the employer’s business."[59] Such contracts are inherently invalid "since the person remain[s] a de facto fully capacitated adult person with only the contractual role of a non-person . . ." as it is impossible to physically transfer self-determination.[60] As Pateman argues:

"The contractarian argument is unassailable all the time it is accepted that abilities can ‘acquire’ an external relation to an individual, and can be treated as if they were property. To treat abilities in this manner is also implicitly to accept that the ‘exchange’ between employer and worker is like any other exchange of material property . . . The answer to the question of how property in the person can be contracted out is that no such procedure is possible. Labour power, capacities or services, cannot be separated from the person of the worker like pieces of property."[61]

Critics of the employment contract advocate consistently applying "the principle behind every trial," i.e., "legal responsibility should be imputed in accordance with de facto responsibility," implying a workplace run jointly by the people who actually work in the firm.[62] The people who actually work in a firm are de facto responsible for the actions of said firm and thus have a legal claim to its outputs, as the contractarian critics argue. "Responsible human action, net value-adding or net value-subtracting, is not de facto transferable."[63] Suppliers (including shareholders), on the other hand, having no de facto responsibility, have no legal claim to the outputs.

While a person may still voluntarily decide to contractually rent himself, just as today he may voluntarily decide to contractually sell himself, in a society where "the principle behind every trial" is consistently applied, neither contract would be legally enforceable, and the rented/sold individual would maintain at all times de jure responsibility for her/his actions, including legal claim to the fruits of their labor. In a modern liberal-capitalist society, the employment contract is enforced while the enslavement contract is not; the former being considered valid because of its consensual/non-coercive nature, and the later being considered inherently invalid, consensual or not. The noted economist Paul Samuelson described this discrepancy.

"Since slavery was abolished, human earning power is forbidden by law to be capitalized. A man is not even free to sell himself; he must rent himself at a wage."[64]

Some advocates of laissez-faire capitalism, among them Robert Nozick, address this inconsistency in modern societies, arguing that a consistently libertarian society would allow and regard as valid consensual/non-coercive enslavement contracts, rejecting the notion of inalienable rights.

"The comparable question about an individual is whether a free system will allow him to sell himself into slavery. I believe that it would."[65]

Others like Murray Rothbard allow for the possibility of debt slavery, asserting that a lifetime labour contract can be broken so long as the slave pays appropriate damages:

"[I]f A has agreed to work for life for B in exchange for 10,000 grams of gold, he will have to return the proportionate amount of property if he terminates the arrangement and ceases to work."[66]

See also

Other works

  • Bruno Leipold, 2022. "Chains and Invisible Threads: Liberty and Domination in Marx's Account of Wage Slavery". Chapter of a larger book by Leipold. Chapter available from Academia.edu with email registration.


References

  1. Bruno Leipold, pp 194-5.
  2. Cited in Bruno Leipold, p 195.
  3. Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Marx Engels Collected Works, volume 3, p. 237. (London: Lawrence & Wishart, 1975–2005), henceforth MECW).
  4. MECW, volume , p. 237.
  5. Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Marx Engels Collected Works, volume 9, p. 203. (London: Lawrence & Wishart, 1975–2005.)
  6. http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1863/theories-surplus-value/ch07.htm |title=Chapter 7 |work=Theories of Surplus Value |author=Frederick Engels |year=1847 |publisher=Marxists.org
  7. P. 211.
  8. Fogel & Engerman, Without Consent or Contract, New York: Norton, 1989, p. 391.
  9. The Height of American Slaves: New Evidence of Slave Nutrition and Health
  10. Debating Slavery: Economy and Society in the Antebellum American South, p. 44
  11. 14.0 14.1 Foner, Eric. 1998. The Story of American Freedom. W. W. Norton & Company. p. 66
  12. 15.0 15.1
  13. 16.0 16.1
  14. 17.0 17.1 p.181-184 Democracy's Discontent By Michael J. Sandel
  15. From Wage Slaves to Wage Workers--Free text
  16. Thoreau, Walden, Penguin, 1983, p.49
  17. E. P. Thompson, The Rise of the English Working Class
  18. Cite error: Invalid <ref> tag; no text was provided for refs named English Working Class p. 912
  19. Cite error: Invalid <ref> tag; no text was provided for refs named Geoffrey Ostergaard p. 133
  20. Cite error: Invalid <ref> tag; no text was provided for refs named Shop Floor p. 37
  21. The highest position slaves ever attained was that of slave minister… A few slaves even rose to be monarchs, such as the slaves who became sultans and founded dynasties in Islām. At a level lower than that of slave ministers were other slaves, such as those in the Roman Empire, the Central Asian Samanid domains, Ch’ing China, and elsewhere, who worked in government offices and administered provinces. … The stereotype that slaves were careless and could only be trusted to do the crudest forms of manual labor was disproved countless times in societies that had different expectations and proper incentives.The sociology of slavery: Slave occupations Encyclopaedia Britannica
  22. Rogue States By Noam Chomsky
  23. Profit Over People by Noam Chomsky
  24. Emma Goldman: A documentary History of the American Years
  25. Fragments of an Anarchist Anthropology p. 37
  26. Kuttner, Op. Cit., p. 153 and p. 154
  27. The Miners' Next Step, pp. 16-17 and p. 15
  28. quoted by Jose Peirats, The CNT in the Spanish Revolution, vol. 2, p. 76
  29. To Have Or to Be? by Erich Fromm
  30. Fredy Perlman: Intro Commodity Fetishism - Infoshop Library
  31. Social Psychology of the Workplace By Shane R. Thye, Edward J. Lawler
  32. Cite error: Invalid <ref> tag; no text was provided for refs named amazon.com
  33. Gramsci, A. (1992) Prison Notebooks. New York : Columbia University Press, pp.233-38
  34. By Greg Toppo, USA TODAY Retrieved October-4-09
  35. Schmidt, Disciplined Minds – A Critical Look at Salaried Professionals And The Soul-Battering System That Shapes Their Lives, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2000, p. 16.
  36. Moral Minds: How Nature Designed Our Universal Sense of Right and Wrong by Marc Hauser
  37. On Just War Theory at West Point Academy: Hauser's theories "could some day provide foundations for a more substantive theory of just war," expanding on some of the existing legal "codifications of these intuitive judgments" that are regularly disregarded by elite power structures. (min 26-30)
  38. An Anarchist FAQ Section E - What do anarchists think causes ecological problems?
  39. Murray Bookchin, Remaking Society, p. 44
  40. Bookchin, The Future of the Ecology Movement, pp. 1–20.
  41. Bookchin, Which Way for the Ecology Movement?, p. 17.
  42. John Clark, The Anarchist Moment, p. 114.
  43. http://library.nothingness.org/articles/anar/en/display/305 A Social Ecology by John Clark
  44. Young, Gary. 1978. Justice and Capitalist Production. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 8, no. 3, p. 448
  45. Nino, Carlos Santiago. 1992. Rights. NYU Press. p.343
  46. interpersonal exchange on The Ludwig von Mises Institute accessed at March 11, 2008
  47. Ellerman, David, Translatio versus Concessio, 16
  48. Ellerman, David, Translatio versus Concessio, 14
  49. Ellerman, David, Translatio versus Concessio, 32
  50. Ellerman, David, Translatio versus Concessio, 27
  51. Ellerman, David, Translatio versus Concessio, 26
  52. Ellerman, David, Inalienable Rights and Contracts, 21
  53. Ellerman, David, Translatio versus Concessio, 2
  54. Man, Economy, and State, vol. I , p. 441


External links