More languages
More actions
(page 12) Tag: Visual edit: Switched |
(page 12) Tag: Visual edit: Switched |
||
Line 61: | Line 61: | ||
Whatever merits this approach might have as an effort to make sense of and continue Marx’s substantive research program, it does, however, encounter certain difficulties whenever it is confronted with the book Marx actually wrote. If it is claimed, for instance, that “Marx has modeled Capital on Hegel’s Logic,”28<ref>Wendling, ''Karl Marx on Technology and Alienation'', 99.</ref> then this modeling seems to have excluded large swaths of the text, including chapters ten, thirteen through fifteen, and twenty-six through thirty-three, together composing over 40 percent of the book. These chapters, as everyone notes, are historical, not logical. And, indeed, scholars inclined toward systematic dialectics seem impelled to segregate these chapters, setting them aside as a “complement” to Marx’s theoretical account;<ref>Heinrich, ''Introduction to the Three Volumes of Karl Marx’s Capital'',</ref> or as “strictly illustrative” and “by no means necessary”;<ref>Arthur, ''The New Dialectic and Marx’s Capital'', 75.</ref> or as asides “interrupting the systematic progression of categories”;<ref> Smith, ''The Logic of Marx’s Capital'', 134.</ref> or as excurses, “tangential to Marx’s principle line of theoretical development”;<ref>Shortall, ''The Incomplete Marx'', 296.</ref> or as “Marx turning away temporarily from the logical unfolding of the categories . . . to make a lengthy digression.”<ref> Ibid., 178.</ref> The end of ''Capital'' seems to be especially embarrassing in this regard. Part eight, on primitive accumulation, is, considered from the point of view of any Hegelian dialectical structure, “tacked on,” and “could be omitted without loss.” <ref>Arthur and White, “Debate,” 130; see also Murray, “Reply to Geert Reuten,” 161.</ref>And yet Marx chose to end the book with this, and even to highlight it by elevating it, in the French edition, to a separate part of eight chapters. | Whatever merits this approach might have as an effort to make sense of and continue Marx’s substantive research program, it does, however, encounter certain difficulties whenever it is confronted with the book Marx actually wrote. If it is claimed, for instance, that “Marx has modeled Capital on Hegel’s Logic,”28<ref>Wendling, ''Karl Marx on Technology and Alienation'', 99.</ref> then this modeling seems to have excluded large swaths of the text, including chapters ten, thirteen through fifteen, and twenty-six through thirty-three, together composing over 40 percent of the book. These chapters, as everyone notes, are historical, not logical. And, indeed, scholars inclined toward systematic dialectics seem impelled to segregate these chapters, setting them aside as a “complement” to Marx’s theoretical account;<ref>Heinrich, ''Introduction to the Three Volumes of Karl Marx’s Capital'',</ref> or as “strictly illustrative” and “by no means necessary”;<ref>Arthur, ''The New Dialectic and Marx’s Capital'', 75.</ref> or as asides “interrupting the systematic progression of categories”;<ref> Smith, ''The Logic of Marx’s Capital'', 134.</ref> or as excurses, “tangential to Marx’s principle line of theoretical development”;<ref>Shortall, ''The Incomplete Marx'', 296.</ref> or as “Marx turning away temporarily from the logical unfolding of the categories . . . to make a lengthy digression.”<ref> Ibid., 178.</ref> The end of ''Capital'' seems to be especially embarrassing in this regard. Part eight, on primitive accumulation, is, considered from the point of view of any Hegelian dialectical structure, “tacked on,” and “could be omitted without loss.” <ref>Arthur and White, “Debate,” 130; see also Murray, “Reply to Geert Reuten,” 161.</ref>And yet Marx chose to end the book with this, and even to highlight it by elevating it, in the French edition, to a separate part of eight chapters. | ||
A survey of this established literature reveals, therefore, that looking to Hegel for the key to the structure of volume one of Capital has so far unlocked only an ideal, counterfactual Capital.<ref>Another sign of this is the stress that many of these authors place on the notion that Marx’s conceptualization of capital “requires the whole three volumes of ''Capital''” (Arthur, ''The New Dialectic and Marx’s Capital'', 34). By way of contrast, I will focus exclusively on the first volume. This difference in focus follows naturally from my emphasis on Marx’s published text— his speech act over and against these authors’ emphasis upon Marx’s research project. Despite the fact that volumes two and three were published well after volume one, they—and especially three—were by and large written before it, and have the appearance of volumes, instead of being rough manuscripts like the ''Grundrisse'', only because of Engels’s intensive editorial work (Krätke, “ ‘Hier bricht das Manuskript sb.’ (Engels): Hat ''Das Kapitaleinen Schluss?''”). One does not have to go so far as Cole, who claimed that “Marx stopped thinking fundamentally about the development of capitalism when he had finished writing Volume I of ''Das Kapital''” (''History of Socialist Thought'', 2:300). Nonetheless, it is undeniable that “Marx did extraordinarily little work on [volumes two and three] in the period [after 1872]. The material used in volumes II and III comes overwhelmingly from the 1850s and 1860s. Sources from the 1870s are exceedingly sparse and of little consequence” (Collins and Abramsky, ''Karl Marx and the British Labour Movement'', 296). The first volume is the only part of ''Capital'' that Marx finished, and it has to be taken as his last word on most issues. More importantly for my purposes, it has to be taken as Marx’s premier act of political speech, his major public statement to the workers’ movement on most matters.</ref> This has been | A survey of this established literature reveals, therefore, that looking to Hegel for the key to the structure of volume one of Capital has so far unlocked only an ideal, counterfactual Capital.<ref>Another sign of this is the stress that many of these authors place on the notion that Marx’s conceptualization of capital “requires the whole three volumes of ''Capital''” (Arthur, ''The New Dialectic and Marx’s Capital'', 34). By way of contrast, I will focus exclusively on the first volume. This difference in focus follows naturally from my emphasis on Marx’s published text— his speech act over and against these authors’ emphasis upon Marx’s research project. Despite the fact that volumes two and three were published well after volume one, they—and especially three—were by and large written before it, and have the appearance of volumes, instead of being rough manuscripts like the ''Grundrisse'', only because of Engels’s intensive editorial work (Krätke, “ ‘Hier bricht das Manuskript sb.’ (Engels): Hat ''Das Kapitaleinen Schluss?''”). One does not have to go so far as Cole, who claimed that “Marx stopped thinking fundamentally about the development of capitalism when he had finished writing Volume I of ''Das Kapital''” (''History of Socialist Thought'', 2:300). Nonetheless, it is undeniable that “Marx did extraordinarily little work on [volumes two and three] in the period [after 1872]. The material used in volumes II and III comes overwhelmingly from the 1850s and 1860s. Sources from the 1870s are exceedingly sparse and of little consequence” (Collins and Abramsky, ''Karl Marx and the British Labour Movement'', 296). The first volume is the only part of ''Capital'' that Marx finished, and it has to be taken as his last word on most issues. More importantly for my purposes, it has to be taken as Marx’s premier act of political speech, his major public statement to the workers’ movement on most matters.</ref> This has been extremely stimulating for certain purposes. The authors of this tendency are quite insightful on Marx’s discussion of value, for example, and there is no doubt that they have, collectively, reinvigorated Marx’s critique of political economy as an agenda for ongoing research. Nonetheless, all of the most sophisticated practitioners of this approach must admit that the dialectic of concepts does not explain why Capital has precisely the order of exposition that it does. Hence, without impugning these authors’ real achievements, or downplaying Hegel’s influence on Marx, we can recognize that another principle of order must be found if we are to understand why ''Capital'' takes the form it does. While it would be foolish to argue that it is Dante, ''not'' Hegel, who provides the key to the structure of Marx’s book, Hegel cannot claim our complete attention. There is room to investigate other influences upon Marx’s “method of presentation.” | ||
If scholarship on the Marx-Hegel relationship has generally shifted from the question of dialectical history to the question of the dialectical systematicity of capital, the scholarship on Marx’s relationship to classical political economy has seen an even greater transformation. In 1941, Henryk Grossman could write that “the dominant opinion sees in Marx only a student of, follower of, or successor to the classical economists,” and then cite everyone from Pareto to , Schumpeter to Hilferding and Dobb.<ref>Grossman, ''Marx, Die Klassische Nationalökonomie und das Problem der Dynamik'', 7.</ref> While one can still find this old “dominant opinion” circulating widely in more recent discussions— especially by non-Marxian economists and analytical Marxists<ref>See, for instance, Howard and King, who claim that “Marx built his political economy upon a critique of his classical predecessors, especially Smith and Ricardo. He refashioned their concepts, corrected what he considered to be their logical defects, reinterpreted results and extended the analysis” (''The Political Economy of Marx'', 40). See also Cohen, ''History, Labour and Freedom'', chap. 11, which presupposes that Marx subscribed to a Ricardian labor theory of value.</ref>—there has been a sea change within Marxological scholarship. What is emphasized in most recent works is | |||
[[Category:Library works by William Claire Roberts]] | [[Category:Library works by William Claire Roberts]] |
Revision as of 07:17, 25 June 2024
Marx’s Inferno: the political theory of Capital | |
---|---|
Author | William Clare Roberts |
Publisher | Princeton University Press |
First published | 2017 |
Type | Book |
C H A P T E R 1
Introduction: Rereading Capital
When word of his death reached New York City, “representatives of the various trades, labor, social, and other organizations” issued a public statement proclaiming that “now it is the duty of all true lovers of liberty to honor the name of Karl Marx.”[1] This call has become, over the course
of the twentieth century, nigh unintelligible. “Liberty” has become the shibboleth of antisocialism and anticommunism. That Marx was ever taken to be a devoted advocate of “the liberation of all downtrodden people,” as these laborers and socialists claimed, seems, not antiquated, but bizarre. Justice, certainly. Progress. Science. Equality. Universal solidarity. But liberty? What has Marx to offer “all true lovers of liberty”?
If this book is to accomplish one thing, it ought to make this eulogy seem not only intelligible but also sensible and reasonable. Marx’s critical theory of capitalism diagnosed the rule of capital as a complex and world- spanning system of domination. He sought, in Capital, to analyze the mechanisms of this system and to reconstruct a notion of freedom adequate to its abolition. In order to be properly appreciated, Marx’s Capital must be recovered as a work of political theory, written in a specific political context, but seeking also to say something of lasting importance about the challenges to—and possibilities for—freedom in the modern world.
My argument is twofold. First, I contend that, in Capital, Marx had a grand aspiration, to write the definitive analysis of what’s wrong with the rule of capital, and that he hung this aspiration on a suitably grand literary framework: rewriting Dante’s Inferno as a descent into the modern “social Hell” of the capitalist mode of production. Dante, of course, staged his own, individual, salvation story, telling us how his encounter with the evil of the world prepared his soul for its journey to blessedness. But his pilgrim was also supposed to be an Everyman, whose descent into damnation and resurrection into grace might be reiterated by all of the faithful. Marx, on the other hand, cast himself as a Virgil for the proletariat, guiding his readers through the lower recesses of the capitalist economic order in order that they might learn not only how this “infernal machine” works, [2] but also what traps to avoid in their efforts to construct a new world.
Second, I argue that in order to understand Marx’s attempt to realize this grand aspiration, Capital is best read as a critical reconstruction of and rejoinder to the other versions of socialism and popular radicalism that predominated in France and England in the 1860s and 1870s, when Marx was composing his magnum opus. These competing discourses—the remnants of Owenism, Fourierism, and Saint-Simonianism,[3] the social republicanism of James Bronterre O’Brien,[4] and, most crucially, the mutualism of Pierre-Joseph Proudhon[5] — were at the forefront of Marx’s concern when he was writing Capital. The foundation of the International Working Men’s Association (IWMA) in 1864,[6] and Marx’s conviction that the group held the seeds of a renewal of revolutionary politics, spurred him to get his thousands of pages of manuscripts and notes into publishable form. He hoped that the book would provide the theoretical guideposts for the resurgent movement. In order for it to achieve this status, Capital had to either co-opt, undermine, or openly confront the existing theoretical commonplaces of the rival camps, which dominated the political landscape that Marx hoped his own outlook would come to occupy. Hence, in the process and for the sake of unfolding Marx’s critique of capitalism,[7] my book examines Marx’s borrowings from and arguments against the other socialists, many of which remain sub rosa to those unfamiliar with the writers in question.
Marx’s grand ambitions and his internecine struggles are not separable from one another, either, but are thoroughly intertwined. The notion that modernity is a “social Hell” was originally suggested by Charles Fourier and his protégé Victor Considérant, and had already been developed in the works of Pierre-Joseph Proudhon into a metaphorical history of humanity’s descent into and escape from the underworld. The moral categories that structure Dante’s Hell—incontinence, force, fraud, and treachery— were common terms in the moral discourse of early socialism. Indeed, much of early socialism, as it emerged from Christian and civic republican discourses, consisted in the application of these moral categories to the social question, and this was a crucial point of contention between Marx and his more moralistic predecessors and contemporaries. Marx’s distinctiveness comes to the fore in that his opponents want either to avoid political economy, or else, like Proudhon, to remain within it. Only Marx, following Dante, sees the necessity of going through political economy in order to get beyond it. And, as in the case of Dante’s pilgrim, this transit is transformative. But Marx’s journey, unlike Dante’s, is supposed to de-personalize and de-moralize. Marx recapitulates Dante’s descent through incontinence, force, fraud, and treachery in order to show that it is capital, as a system of all-around domination, that is responsible for these evils, not the individuals dominated by capital.
Thus my book is only able to trace either of these two threads by tracing both. By considering together Marx’s context and his designs, this study shows how Marx’s fights with other socialist theorists in the early years of the IWMA were transmuted by him into Capital, and reveals the ambition of Capital to lay bare, for the first time, the inner workings of the capitalist mode of production and the political economy that analyzes it, as a Hell into which the proletariat must descend in order to free themselves and the world.
Reading Capital as Political Theory
My argument takes its orientation from some of the literary aspects of Marx’s book—its use of tropes and metaphors, its allusions and citations. For all that, however, I do not treat Capital as a work of literature. Rather, I treat it as a work of political theory. Its tropes, metaphors, allusions, and citations are approached as signs to be interpreted, as the linguistic traces of intuitions that can be fleshed out in theoretical terms. When socialists and communists, including Marx, call capital a vampire, they do so because the metaphor seems to them an apt one. And the aptitude of the metaphor can be discussed and articulated in language that is not itself merely an elaboration of the metaphor. The sense that capital is parasitical upon something—labor—that is both more primary to human existence and more natural and lively than is capital can be spelled out. These intuitions have their own implicit presuppositions, and these can be made explicit. The judgment against capital implied by the vampire metaphor can, by this process, come to be considered independently of the metaphor itself, and can be assessed as more or less cogent.
The metaphors, tropes, and formulas circulated within a discourse are the anchors of its common sensibility, the moments that give to an utterance an immediate plausibility or attractiveness within a certain community of writers and readers, speakers and listeners, and an immediate outlandishness to members of other communities. Political speech is often an exercise in recollecting, rehearsing, burnishing, and deploying such familiarities, for the sake of signaling one’s allegiances and rallying one’s allies. It recalls people to their prior commitments and to the shared narratives that make sense of their world by orienting them in it.
In the South Dakota of my youth, for example, it was de rigueur for political speeches and ads to refer to at least one of two scenes: a rancher riding and surveying his range, or a handful of farmers exchanging news and gathering supplies on the Main Street of a small town. The figure of the rancher bespoke the assumption that the land ought to be controlled and supervised by independent men, who could be trusted and expected to take care of things themselves. The tableau of the farming town was to remind the audience of the trust and mutual reliance that exists among neighbors, who know one another for what they are. Whether spoken, written, or depicted by actors on TV, these political tropes signaled adherence to a common sense of what political life was about— its parameters and stakes—in a sparsely populated prairie state, where the native population had been subjugated and confined to reservations and poverty, and where the upsurge of political Christianism had yet to make significant inroads. Every discursive community has such anchoring homilies.
By contrast with the mere reiteration of these metaphors and tropes, however, the attempt to articulate a nonmetaphorical discourse around them is the playing out of a rope that gives a speaker or writer some measure of mobility among communities. Rather than simply stringing together immediately plausible turns of phrase, the watchwords and catchphrases of one’s closest circle of interlocutors, a writer might try to make those watchwords and catchphrases understandable to a wider circle of readers, to explicate the sense of them, to motivate them by appeal to experiences and arguments drawn from other communities or common to many communities. By this effort, the anchoring homilies of one’s local political dialect are maintained, but are also rendered less parochial. They enter into relations with previously alien metaphors and tropes. The discourse anchored in them attains a more or less limited independence from them, a flexibility and mobility and adaptability that it otherwise would have lacked.
Political theory is, according to this way of thinking, the effort to escape being sunk by one’s own anchors. Hence, to read Capital as political theory is to show how Marx tried therein to give a more cosmopolitan sense to particular metaphors and tropes that were, in their origins, provincial to the socialism and popular radicalism of the nineteenth century. [8] Such a project requires acknowledging where Marx’s linguistic materials came from, and what associations his words would likely have called to mind in the context of their utterance. But it also insists that Marx’s work cannot be dispersed into that context. The single-minded internalism that seeks to reconstruct an author’s work on the sole basis of what that author wrote is prone to anachronism, to reading works of the past as if they were addressing the reader’s present-day concerns and preoccupations. As Gregory Claeys has noted, “Marx and Engels were relative latecomers to a debate [over socialism] that was thirty years old before they began to consider seriously its central issues.” In their efforts to include themselves in and influence the direction of that debate, “they incorporated into their own thought many hidden assumptions and even covert first principles which occasionally emerged to the discursive surface, but as often as not remained half-disclosed if not well buried.”[9] These half-disclosed references to earlier writers and controversies will not reveal themselves to someone who does not look beyond the various editions of Marx and Engels’s collected works to the writings of the other socialists they read and argued with. [10] On the other hand, as helpful as a familiarity with the context is for grounding the study of works of political theory, and as important as contextual considerations are for the argument of this book, context is not everything. If a work of political theory gains much of its sense and comprehensibility from remaining within “the parameters of a given political language or . . . certain linguistic conventions,”[11] its cogency or power tends to come more from its idiosyncrasies: its exceptional formal coherence, scope, or rigor. Contextual scholarship has immensely enriched our understanding of British political thought, has resuscitated the tradition of republicanism, and has brought new attention to neglected figures like James Harrington. It has not, however, diminished the stature of Hobbes’s Leviathan or Locke’s Treatises. Nor should it. If the “great books” lose a vital quotient of their sense when they are ripped from their contexts and pitted against one another on the barren plain of “the history of the West,” approaching them in the settings from which they emerged does not entail denying their greatness.
I am convinced that Marx’s Capital is one of the great works of political theory. It identifies and analyzes an interrelated set of political problems that are either invisible to or wished away by virtually every other book in the canon of great works, no matter how one might expand that canon in other directions. It does so by taking seriously the experiences and complaints of wage laborers, but also by subjecting those experiences and complaints to a sort of immanent criticism. For this reason, I think the greatness of Capital, as well as much of the sense of its argument, emerges only or best when it is read against the background of the socialisms with which Marx was contending, socialisms that grew much more directly out of the everyday political discourse of the workers’ movement. Reading Capital against the backdrop of this political language of workers requires some reconstruction of the context in which it was written and the audience to whom it was addressed. But discussion of this context, and of the political languages that comprise it, is a means to an end, not an end in itself. Hence, this book lacks the historical and documentary scope of a full- blooded contextual history of Marx’s political thought.[12] It makes up for this lack, hopefully, by the depth of attention it gives to the text and argument of Capital, and by the reconstruction of certain strands of argument—regarding money, exploitation, exchange relations, and such—central to the non-Marxian socialisms of Marx’s day.
This question of context is closely related to another. One of the difficulties faced in trying to read Capital as political theory is that Marx’s texts have become anchors for many who write about him or who try to continue his project. That is, Marx’s writings acquired, over the course of the century after his death, the opacity and immediacy of metaphors and formulas, self- explanatory or self- refuting, depending upon the party to which one belonged. In order to show that Marx was doing political theory, therefore, it is also necessary to do political theory with Marx. In other words, one must embed his concepts in other discourses, translating his claims into languages not his own. This carries risks, of course. In trying to clarify and bring out the force of Marx’s assertions and arguments, for example, I have drawn significantly on the reconstructions of republicanism offered by Quentin Skinner and Philip Pettit.[13] I think their explication of republican freedom as non-domination tracks much more closely the range and types of Marx’s concerns than does the more traditional attribution to Marx of a positive conception of freedom as collective self-realization or collective self-mastery. This use of contemporary neo-republican arguments exposes me, however, to the very anachronism that I have tried to ward off by means of contextualizing Marx’s arguments. It is one thing, after all, to argue that Marx and Engels were “more indebted to their socialist predecessors than has usually been conceded,” and that a central element of this debt consists in the transmission, via the early socialists, of elements of eighteenth-century republicanism into Marxism.[14] It is another thing altogether to claim that freedom as non-domination was one of Marx’s central political ideals. Such a claim seems to imply a teleology according to which nineteenth- century socialists, including Marx, knew not what they said; their words implied concepts that would not be developed and properly clarified until the present generation of academic political theorists roused the sense slumbering in the dusty chambers of nineteenth-century books.
However, this misperceives the role played by contemporary republican political theory in the reconstruction of the past (or, at least, forecloses roles that it might play). The rise of neo-republican political theory stems directly from research on the history of political thought. That research, however, did not really cross “the great divide into the nineteenth century.”[15] The republicanism that has been reconstructed as neo-republicanism is an aristocratic republicanism, which predated the great emancipation movements of the nineteenth century. There is a significant literature devoted to arguing that the historical and social circumscription of the original has bequeathed conceptual limitations to the revival.[16] As Alex Gourevitch has noted, however,
The best chance republicanism had of “transcending” its aristocratic origins and of developing an egalitarian critique of enslavement and subjection was when someone other than society’s dominant elite used republican language to articulate their concerns. This is precisely what happened when nineteenth-century artisans and wage-laborers appropriated the inherited concepts of independence and virtue and applied them to the world of labor relations. The attempt to universalize the language of republican liberty, and the conceptual innovations that took place in the process, were their contribution to this political tradition.[17]
By pursuing the republican tradition into the nineteenth century, and into the writings of plebeian radicals and socialists, one might, therefore, find that traditional republican concerns with freedom, status, and virtue are capable of far- reaching and surprising extensions and transformations. This, in turn, throws into relief the limits of neo-republicanism as a representative of the republican tradition. Hence, the juxtaposition of nineteenth-century radical and socialist deployments of republican terminology with neo-republican understandings of the scope and meaning of republican liberty need not imply that the latter are the destiny of the former. This juxtaposition can just as well serve to highlight the blind spots and narrowness of the contemporary reconstruction of republicanism.
By pursuing these republican themes further, through Marx’s immanent criticism of socialism, I hope to portray Marx as delineating an alternative republicanism, one that has a family resemblance to the neo-republicanism presently on the table, but that departs from an analysis of the social form of modern life, rather than holding fast to the purely political constitution of the public sphere. This reconstruction of the political theory of Marx’s Capital will inevitably flatten somewhat both the historical diversity of socialist and republican political languages from which Marx departed and the complexity of the neo-republicanism that claims to develop and clarify those languages. If I am able to bring out the specificity and force of Marx’s project in Capital, these trade-offs are acceptable to me.
Reading Capital As Political Theory
Because political theory is a certain sort of political speech, and political speech is essentially an intervention on one side or another of some political question, the rhetoric, form, and address of a work of political theory are internal to the content of its argument. Rather than being read as a work of political theory, however, Capital is generally approached either as a treatise of socialist economics or as a work of social theory. If Capital is to be regarded as a work of social or economic theory, then its audience is thereby cast in the role of the student. The text is supposed to be fundamentally didactic, and its rhetoric and form are reduced to matters of style, external to the real content of the book, which might be formalized without any substantive loss.
Within Marxological literature, therefore, considerations of the structure of Capital are generally posed in the guise of questions about “the method of presentation.” This picks up on Marx’s distinction, in the afterword to the second German edition, between “the method of presentation [Darstellungsweise] [and] the method of research [Forschungsweise].”[18] Marx draws that distinction in the midst of differentiating his method of inquiry from the “Hegelian sophistry” of which his German reviewers had accused him. Marx denies that his method is Hegelian, writing that research
has to appropriate the material in detail, to analyze its different forms of development, and to track down their inner connection. Only after this work has been done can the real movement be appropriately presented. If this is done successfully, if the life of the material is now reflected ideally, then it may appear as if we are dealing with an a priori construction.[19]
Marx is pretty clearly associating a priori constructions with Hegel here, or assuming that whatever appears to be an a priori construction will, for this reason, appear to be a “Hegelian sophistry.” Nonetheless, at least since Lenin first read Hegel’s Logic, readers of Marx have been trying to understand the argument and form of Capital as some sort of application or modification or instantiation or performance of Hegelian dialectics.[20] An older manner of doing so, taking its cues from some of Engels’s remarks,[21] understood Marx’s presentation to be a sort of dialectical history of the development of capitalism, more or less “corrected” for the sake of logical clarity.[22] This approach has largely fallen out of favor, in part because it seemed to require the imputation of a “secular theodicy” to Marx,>[23] in part because the textual evidence for some of its central claims evaporated upon publication of scholarly editions of Marx’s works— for example, the era of “simple commodity production,” supposedly discussed in part one of Capital, was in fact wholly the invention of Engels.[24] This dialectical historicism has been supplanted by an approach that is often called “systematic dialectics.”[25] Marx’s argument in Capital is supposed to be systematic because the object of his research, capital, “is a totality where every part has to be complemented by others to be what it is,” and which “cannot be comprehended immediately.” Marx’s “methodological problem,” therefore,
is a matter of how to articulate a complex concept that cannot be grasped by some sort of immediate intuition. In doing so [he has] to make a start with some aspect of it. But the exposition can reconstruct the whole from a particular starting point because we can move logically from one element to another along a chain of internal relations; in strict logic if the very meaning of an element is at issue . . . or with a fair degree of confidence if material conditions of existence are involved. [26]
This logical movement along a chain of internal relations is dialectics. Since this dialectic is only supposed to articulate the systematic nature of capital, the systematic dialectics of Marx’s method of presentation has no bearing on the course of history. Any secular theodicy is avoided, and the reader can honor Marx’s own programmatic statements, such as his claim that he is “only out to present the internal organization of the capitalist mode of production, its ideal average, as it were.”[27]
Whatever merits this approach might have as an effort to make sense of and continue Marx’s substantive research program, it does, however, encounter certain difficulties whenever it is confronted with the book Marx actually wrote. If it is claimed, for instance, that “Marx has modeled Capital on Hegel’s Logic,”28[28] then this modeling seems to have excluded large swaths of the text, including chapters ten, thirteen through fifteen, and twenty-six through thirty-three, together composing over 40 percent of the book. These chapters, as everyone notes, are historical, not logical. And, indeed, scholars inclined toward systematic dialectics seem impelled to segregate these chapters, setting them aside as a “complement” to Marx’s theoretical account;[29] or as “strictly illustrative” and “by no means necessary”;[30] or as asides “interrupting the systematic progression of categories”;[31] or as excurses, “tangential to Marx’s principle line of theoretical development”;[32] or as “Marx turning away temporarily from the logical unfolding of the categories . . . to make a lengthy digression.”[33] The end of Capital seems to be especially embarrassing in this regard. Part eight, on primitive accumulation, is, considered from the point of view of any Hegelian dialectical structure, “tacked on,” and “could be omitted without loss.” [34]And yet Marx chose to end the book with this, and even to highlight it by elevating it, in the French edition, to a separate part of eight chapters.
A survey of this established literature reveals, therefore, that looking to Hegel for the key to the structure of volume one of Capital has so far unlocked only an ideal, counterfactual Capital.[35] This has been extremely stimulating for certain purposes. The authors of this tendency are quite insightful on Marx’s discussion of value, for example, and there is no doubt that they have, collectively, reinvigorated Marx’s critique of political economy as an agenda for ongoing research. Nonetheless, all of the most sophisticated practitioners of this approach must admit that the dialectic of concepts does not explain why Capital has precisely the order of exposition that it does. Hence, without impugning these authors’ real achievements, or downplaying Hegel’s influence on Marx, we can recognize that another principle of order must be found if we are to understand why Capital takes the form it does. While it would be foolish to argue that it is Dante, not Hegel, who provides the key to the structure of Marx’s book, Hegel cannot claim our complete attention. There is room to investigate other influences upon Marx’s “method of presentation.”
If scholarship on the Marx-Hegel relationship has generally shifted from the question of dialectical history to the question of the dialectical systematicity of capital, the scholarship on Marx’s relationship to classical political economy has seen an even greater transformation. In 1941, Henryk Grossman could write that “the dominant opinion sees in Marx only a student of, follower of, or successor to the classical economists,” and then cite everyone from Pareto to , Schumpeter to Hilferding and Dobb.[36] While one can still find this old “dominant opinion” circulating widely in more recent discussions— especially by non-Marxian economists and analytical Marxists[37]—there has been a sea change within Marxological scholarship. What is emphasized in most recent works is
- ↑ “Reported Death of Karl Marx,” New York Times, March 16, 1883.
- ↑ Jameson, Representing “Capital,” 146.
- ↑ Booth, Saint-Simon and Saint-Simonism; Iggers, The Cult of Authority: The Political Philosophy of the Saint-Simonians; Harrison, Robert Owen and the Owenites in Britain and America; Garnett, Co-Operation and the Owenite Socialist Communities in Britain, 1825– 45; Claeys, Machinery, Money, and the Millennium; Claeys, Citizens and Saints; Pilbeam, French Socialists before Marx; Pilbeam, Saint-Simonians in Nineteenth-Century France
- ↑ Plummer, Bronterre; Claeys, Citizens and Saints, pt. III.
- ↑ Puech, Le Proudhonisme dans l’Association internationale des travailleurs; Hoffman, Revolutionary Justice; Prichard, Justice, Order, and Anarchy; Vincent, Proudhon and the Rise of French Republican Socialism.
- ↑ Collins and Abramsky, Karl Marx and the British Labour Movement; Braunthal, History of the International; Stekloff, History of the First International.
- ↑ Throughout, I will use “capitalism” as an umbrella term for those “societies in which the capitalist mode of production reigns” (Marx, Capital, 1:125; MEGA, II.6:17; MEGA, II.7:19).
- ↑ Instead of seeing political theory in this way—as “party ideas” raised to the level of theory—some will insist that political theory is “always in one way or another constitutional theory; it always necessarily turns on the framing of a constitution” (Jameson, Representing “Capital,” 139). On this basis, they will conclude that Capital “has no political conclusions” (ibid.). I will argue in chapter 7 that even on this understanding of political theory, Capital implies more about the future constitution of communism than is often allowed.
- ↑ Claeys, Citizens and Saints,
- ↑ The ongoing publication of the second Marx- Engels Gesamtausgabe (MEGA) has been a boon for scholars, but scholarly editions of Marx and Engels’s works will not push the study of their thought onto the wider terrain of its context. Luckily, I have been able to draw upon the work of a number of historians of political thought who have mapped some of this background, including: Iggers, The Cult of Authority: The Political Philosophy of the Saint- Simonians; Loubère, Louis Blanc: His Life and His Contribution to the Rise of French Jacobin- Socialism; Harrison, Robert Owen and the Owenites in Britain and America; Garnett, Co-Operation and the Owenite Socialist Communities in Britain, 1825–45; Goodwin, Social Science and Utopia; Taylor, The Political Ideas of the Utopian Socialists; Vincent, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon and the Rise of French Republican Socialism; Thompson, The People’s Science; Thompson, The Market and Its Critics; Claeys, Machinery, Money, and the Millennium; Claeys, Citizens and Saints; Pilbeam, French Socialists before Marx; Lattek, Revolutionary Refugees; Pilbeam, Saint-Simonians in Nineteenth-Century France.
- ↑ Claeys, Citizens and Saints, 17.
- ↑ Although it is rather limited in its exploration of context, especially in its second volume, the most sensitive, thorough, and accurate account of Marx as a political thinker remains Richard Hunt’s The Political Ideas of Marx and Engels, 2 vols. (1974, 1984). Christine Lattek’s recent book, Revolutionary Refugees, goes much deeper into the context of Hunt’s first volume, but this does not displace Hunt’s theses about Marx, but rather confirms them in the main. The general shortcoming of works that examine Marx’s relationship with other socialists is that of blind partisanship. The Marxists tend not to go beyond what Marx says about other socialists (e.g., Draper, Karl Marx’s Theory of Revolution). Those who look at the other socialists tend to be defenders of those socialists against Marx’s criticisms (e.g., Hoffman, Revolutionary Justice; Menuelle, Marx, Lecteur de Proudhon).
- ↑ The literature on republican political thought and neo- republicanism is vast. The leading edge of republicanism’s revival in its contemporary form includes: Skinner, “The Idea of Negative Liberty”; Skinner, Liberty before Liberalism; Pettit, Republicanism.
- ↑ Claeys, Citizens and Saints, 51.
- ↑ Ibid., 6.
- ↑ Criticisms along these lines can be found in: Ghosh, “From Republican to Liberal Liberty”; Kapust, “Skinner, Pettit and Livy: The Conflict of the Orders and the Ambiguity of Republican Liberty”; Krause, “Beyond Non-Domination: Agency, Inequality, and the Meaning of Freedom”; Maddox, “The Limits of Neo-Roman Liberty”; Markell, “The Insufficiency of Non- Domination”; McCormick, “Machiavelli against Republicanism: On the Cambridge School’s ‘Guiccardian Moments’ ”; Wood, “Why It Matters.” Crucial for my own thinking on this matter is Alex’s Gourevitch’s articulation of what he calls the paradox of slavery and freedom (From Slavery to the Cooperative Commonwealth, chap. 1).
- ↑ Gourevitch, From Slavery to the Cooperative Commonwealth, 14.
- ↑ Capital, 1:102; MEGA, II.6:709. Marx himself takes the distinction over from the review of Capital by I. I. Kaufman in the European Messenger (Capital, 1:100; MEGA, II.6:707).
- ↑ Capital, 1:102; MEGA, II.6:709.
- ↑ Lenin’s famous “aphorism” is that “It is impossible completely to understand Marx’s Capital, and especially its first chapter, without having thoroughly studied and understood the whole of Hegel’s Logic. Consequently, half a century later none of the Marxists understood Marx!!” (Collected Works, 38:180).
- ↑ See Engels’s review, for Das Volk, of Marx’s Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy (MECW, 16:475).
- ↑ A relatively sophisticated representative of this approach would be Ronald Meek, Studies in the Labour Theory of Value.
- ↑ Elster, “Marxism, Functionalism and Game Theory,” 206.
- ↑ For details, see Arthur, “Engels as Interpreter of Marx’s Economics.”
- ↑ There are far too many works that might be justifiably included under this heading to list them all here. A representative sample might include the following: Albritton and Simoulidis, New Dialectics and Political Economy; Albritton, Dialectics and Deconstruction in Political Economy; Arthur, Dialectics of Labour; Elson, Value: The Representation of Labour in Capitalism; Roth and Eldred, Guide to Marx’s “Capital”; Hunt, Analytical and Dialectical Marxism; Lebowitz, Following Marx; Lebowitz, Beyond Capital; McCarney, Hegel on History; Murray, Marx’s Theory of Scientific Knowledge; Norman and Sayers, Hegel, Marx, and Dialectic; Postone, Time, Labor, and Social Domination; Reuten, “The Interconnection of Systematic Dialectics and Historical Materialism”; Bell, Capitalism and the Dialectic; Williams, Value, Social Form and the State. See also the bibliography in Arthur, The New Dialectic and Marx’s Capital. Much of the work done in the wake of Backhaus’s Marx und die Marxistische Orthodoxie might also be included; see, for example, the statement on method in Heinrich, Introduction to the Three Volumes of Karl Marx’s Capital, 30–32.
- ↑ Arthur, The New Dialectic and Marx’s Capital, 24– 25.
- ↑ Capital, 3:970; MEGA, II.15:806.
- ↑ Wendling, Karl Marx on Technology and Alienation, 99.
- ↑ Heinrich, Introduction to the Three Volumes of Karl Marx’s Capital,
- ↑ Arthur, The New Dialectic and Marx’s Capital, 75.
- ↑ Smith, The Logic of Marx’s Capital, 134.
- ↑ Shortall, The Incomplete Marx, 296.
- ↑ Ibid., 178.
- ↑ Arthur and White, “Debate,” 130; see also Murray, “Reply to Geert Reuten,” 161.
- ↑ Another sign of this is the stress that many of these authors place on the notion that Marx’s conceptualization of capital “requires the whole three volumes of Capital” (Arthur, The New Dialectic and Marx’s Capital, 34). By way of contrast, I will focus exclusively on the first volume. This difference in focus follows naturally from my emphasis on Marx’s published text— his speech act over and against these authors’ emphasis upon Marx’s research project. Despite the fact that volumes two and three were published well after volume one, they—and especially three—were by and large written before it, and have the appearance of volumes, instead of being rough manuscripts like the Grundrisse, only because of Engels’s intensive editorial work (Krätke, “ ‘Hier bricht das Manuskript sb.’ (Engels): Hat Das Kapitaleinen Schluss?”). One does not have to go so far as Cole, who claimed that “Marx stopped thinking fundamentally about the development of capitalism when he had finished writing Volume I of Das Kapital” (History of Socialist Thought, 2:300). Nonetheless, it is undeniable that “Marx did extraordinarily little work on [volumes two and three] in the period [after 1872]. The material used in volumes II and III comes overwhelmingly from the 1850s and 1860s. Sources from the 1870s are exceedingly sparse and of little consequence” (Collins and Abramsky, Karl Marx and the British Labour Movement, 296). The first volume is the only part of Capital that Marx finished, and it has to be taken as his last word on most issues. More importantly for my purposes, it has to be taken as Marx’s premier act of political speech, his major public statement to the workers’ movement on most matters.
- ↑ Grossman, Marx, Die Klassische Nationalökonomie und das Problem der Dynamik, 7.
- ↑ See, for instance, Howard and King, who claim that “Marx built his political economy upon a critique of his classical predecessors, especially Smith and Ricardo. He refashioned their concepts, corrected what he considered to be their logical defects, reinterpreted results and extended the analysis” (The Political Economy of Marx, 40). See also Cohen, History, Labour and Freedom, chap. 11, which presupposes that Marx subscribed to a Ricardian labor theory of value.