Toggle menu
Toggle personal menu
Not logged in
Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits.

Dialectical materialism: Difference between revisions

From ProleWiki, the proletarian encyclopedia
(added Misconceptions section)
Tag: Visual edit
Tag: Visual edit
 
(One intermediate revision by the same user not shown)
Line 41: Line 41:
=== Transformation of quantity into quality and vice versa ===
=== Transformation of quantity into quality and vice versa ===
Also called progress by leaps and bounds.
Also called progress by leaps and bounds.
It should be understood that progress does not mean being progressive, but merely that ''things change;'' that something that once existed does not anymore, it has morphed into a new thing. Once a critical point is reached, then change happens meaningfully. We see for example that feudalism was not deposed by reforms in parliament or to the monarchy, but by decisive revolution headed by bourgeois and capitalists. The same thing can be said about something as simple as water: when heated, water does not gradually make more steam the more it's heated. It will start off not making any steam, and then once it reaches a certain point, steam starts. This means something can stay still for years (such as a communist party not making any progress), and then suddenly make progress (such as the communist party suddenly seeing a surge in new members as the contradictions of capitalism worsen).


All change has a quantitative aspect, that is, an aspect of mere increase or decrease which does not alter the nature of that which changes. But quantitative change, increase or decrease, cannot go on indefinitely. At a certain point it always leads to a qualitative change; and at that critical point, the qualitative change takes place relatively suddenly.
All change has a quantitative aspect, that is, an aspect of mere increase or decrease which does not alter the nature of that which changes. But quantitative change, increase or decrease, cannot go on indefinitely. At a certain point it always leads to a qualitative change; and at that critical point, the qualitative change takes place relatively suddenly.
Line 65: Line 67:


Dialectical materialism is distinct from [[dualism]]. Dualism frames the world as a pair of mutually negating forces -- that of idea and matter, consciousness and being -- and that correspondingly, phenomena also fall into two categories: the ideal and the material, which negate each other, and contend against each other, so that the development of nature and society is a constant struggle between ideal and material phenomena. Dialectical materialism views these opposed forces as distinct parts of the whole substance. Like the two sides of a coin.<ref>{{Citation|author=Joseph Stalin|year=1907|title=Anarchism Or Socialism?|title-url=https://en.prolewiki.org/wiki/Library:Anarchism_or_socialism%3F|chapter=Chapter II The Materialist Theory|chapter-url=https://en.prolewiki.org/wiki/Library:Anarchism_or_socialism%3F#The_materialist_theory|city=Moscow|publisher=Foreign Languages Publishing House|mia=https://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/stalin/works/1906/12/x01.htm}}</ref>
Dialectical materialism is distinct from [[dualism]]. Dualism frames the world as a pair of mutually negating forces -- that of idea and matter, consciousness and being -- and that correspondingly, phenomena also fall into two categories: the ideal and the material, which negate each other, and contend against each other, so that the development of nature and society is a constant struggle between ideal and material phenomena. Dialectical materialism views these opposed forces as distinct parts of the whole substance. Like the two sides of a coin.<ref>{{Citation|author=Joseph Stalin|year=1907|title=Anarchism Or Socialism?|title-url=https://en.prolewiki.org/wiki/Library:Anarchism_or_socialism%3F|chapter=Chapter II The Materialist Theory|chapter-url=https://en.prolewiki.org/wiki/Library:Anarchism_or_socialism%3F#The_materialist_theory|city=Moscow|publisher=Foreign Languages Publishing House|mia=https://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/stalin/works/1906/12/x01.htm}}</ref>
=== Progress by leaps and bounds ===
Progress happens by leaps. It should be understood that progress does not mean being progressive, but merely that ''things change;'' that something that once existed does not anymore, it has morphed into a new thing. Once a critical point is reached, then change happens meaningfully. We see for example that feudalism was not deposed by reforms in parliament or to the monarchy, but by revolution headed by bourgeois and capitalists. The same thing can be said about something as simple as water: when heated, water does not gradually make more steam the more it's heated. It will start off not making any steam, and then once it reaches a certain point, steam starts. This means something can stay still for years (such as a communist party not making any progress), and then suddenly make progress (such as the communist party suddenly seeing a surge in new members as the contradictions of capitalism worsen).
'''Quantitative change turns into qualitative change'''. Water is gradually heated to 100° Celcius, which is quantitative (it can be counted). It starts producing steam at this temperature, which is qualitative (it can be described but not counted). In other domains, this quantitative change can take years, decades or even centuries. Dialectics does not say that change must happen after a certain time or in a certain timeframe.


== Examples ==
== Examples ==
Line 84: Line 81:


=== Dialectics only apply to political science ===
=== Dialectics only apply to political science ===
Some people believe hat dialectics and dialectical materialism only apply to political science, or even more specifically to Marxism alone and are just one way of seeing the world out of many competing but equally valid frameworks.
Some people believe that dialectics and dialectical materialism only apply to political science, or even more specifically to Marxism alone and are just one way of seeing the world out of many competing but equally valid frameworks.


Dialectical materialism is the most advanced way to study and understand the world as of yet because it follows scientific principles, is derived from natural phenomena, and simply is the most able framework to explain the objective nature of the world (in terms of correct analyses and predictions). It is not specifically Marxist either and can be used by anyone. Dialectical materialism is a framework to study the world, and works as a "base" to build upon.
Dialectical materialism is the most advanced way to study and understand the world as of yet because it follows scientific principles, is derived from natural phenomena, and simply is the most able framework to explain the objective nature of the world (in terms of correct analyses and predictions). It is not specifically Marxist either and can be used by anyone. Dialectical materialism is a framework to study the world, and works as a "base" to build upon.

Latest revision as of 17:18, 19 August 2024

Dialectical materialism is a philosophical and scientific worldview based on general principles derived from natural phenomena.[1] It is a scientific methodology developed from the principles of dialectics and materialism, and is one of the theoretical foundations of Marxism.[2] It's a development from Hegel's dialectical principles, which were extremely useful, but ultimately deviated towards idealism.[3]

Although it was a method conceived by Marx and Engels, the term dialectical materialism was never actually used by either, but appropriately summarizes their philosophical outlook. In the preface and second chapter of Socialism: utopian and scientific, Engels calls it "modern materialism".

Idealist thinking, namely metaphysics, posits the world around us as a collection of unchanging, fixed things. This cause much friction with reality as the real world follows dialectical materialism. Reality is changing and moving always. Ideas can motivate men to move mountains. But they can only do so if their material conditions give them the tools capable of doing so. Conversely, it is very easy, especially with the modern invention of various kinds of diggers, movers and earth shaker machines to move mountains. But almost none get moved. And what few that do, are only moved for strip mining and other forms of capital extraction.

Per Wayne Au's A Marxist Education, a basic summary of dialectical materialism's elements

  • asserts that the material world exists outside of human consciousness of it;
  • sees everything as in constant motion;
  • understands contradiction as the basis for all movement, development, and change;
  • sees everything as related and connected, where even opposites make up a relational whole;
  • rejects “either/or” and instead sees “and/both,” relationally;
  • sees quantity and quality, and their transformation into each other, as part of the process of development;
  • asserts that there are negative (destructive) and positive (conservative) sides to any contradiction;
  • holds that the resolution of a contradiction contains within it both the negation (destruction) of the original relationship and the negation of that negation, which is a new relationship (synthesis) at a different level of development;
  • understands the new relationship created in the resolution of a contradiction as carrying aspects of the old relationship within it (sublation);
  • sees the external conditions of a process as playing a strong, sometimes determining role in which internal contradiction is resolved;
  • asserts that the development of a process happens in a spiral, not in a straight line.

History[edit | edit source]

For more information, see idealism and materialism.

To understand how dialectical materialism came to exist, it is necessary to briefly go through how both of those components came to exist. In ancient Greece, dialectics was the name given to the art of argumentation. It was considered that in the course of an argument, rich in fertile ideas, the opinions of the disputing parties underwent a change and that something new and of a higher nature resulted.

The ancient Greeks also theorized about materialism but, at the time, materialism referred to the idea that everything is made of matter. They said that everything is made of tiny particles invisible to the naked eye, and that the properties of these atoms made the properties of the resulting object. For example, oil atoms were big and smooth, and vinegar atoms were very small and pointy. They were not entirely wrong (we later discovered atoms and reused their term, but the properties of actual atoms and what the Greeks thought atoms were are very different), but their meaning of materialism was not any more developed than that.

The Ancient Greeks were but one example, and idealism still permeated their cultures. They theorized, for example, that since everything is made of matter, then the gods must live on Earth somewhere -- rather than completely dispelling the ideas of gods (which is idealism), they tried to fit them into their philosophy.

Starting around the Enlightenment (late 18th century Europe), science emerged as a field -- with its rules and methods -- mostly led by nobles who had the time and means to do scientific experiments. These nobles were the first materialists, so-called metaphysical (beyond physics) as they did not yet possess the full knowledge necessary to understand dialectics since they were just starting out on scientific experiments in a world still dominated by idealism and feudalism.

Later on, philosopher Hegel used dialectics to describe the progress of ideas (thoughts) through contradiction, the process of its development toward a supreme and absolute spirit.[4] Hegel's fundamental question was: where do our ideas come from? How come this or that person had the idea to invent, say, the telephone? How come we didn't have the idea for it earlier? His answer was God, though in that case "God" is more of a concept that means "we may never know".

Marx and Engels were first inspired by Hegel's works and ideas, but later developed a better understanding of reality and its progress and development by applying the dialectical logic to material reality, observing the historical development of society. They put dialectic back right-side up, by divorcing it from its idealist roots and correctly associating it with materialism. To the question of where do our ideas come from? Dialectical materialists reply: from the brain, as the result of a chemical interaction. But moreover from our material conditions; the reality in which we live. Indeed, we know for example that the Ancient Greeks had experimented with steam machines. Yet they didn't use them for industrial production, and steam only gained traction in the industrial revolution when we found out about its power output. Idealists would say that the idea already existed in the time of the Ancient Greeks, but the fact that they did not use steam technology (and it was limited to a couple experiments) shows us material conditions are more important than having the right idea. Essentially, the possibilities of steam did not fit into the Greek mode of production, whose societies by and large relied on slave labour.

It would be wrong to say that dialectical materialism is only the logical progression of Hegelian dialectics. Dialectical materialism has its own rules, methods and roots that set it apart from Hegel's idealist dialectics. It could not have existed meaningfully earlier in time, as the material conditions and the dialectic was not sufficiently advanced for these ideas to take hold. This is an entirely dialectical observation, and a good example of what material dialectics are.

Most of what dialectical materialism is, comes directly from Hegel. Where Marx and Engels innovated was in two major ways. The relationship between quantity and quality. And the reorientation of the the primary mover being the material, rather than spiritual, or ideal realm. [5]

Laws of dialectics[edit | edit source]

Transformation of quantity into quality and vice versa[edit | edit source]

Also called progress by leaps and bounds.

It should be understood that progress does not mean being progressive, but merely that things change; that something that once existed does not anymore, it has morphed into a new thing. Once a critical point is reached, then change happens meaningfully. We see for example that feudalism was not deposed by reforms in parliament or to the monarchy, but by decisive revolution headed by bourgeois and capitalists. The same thing can be said about something as simple as water: when heated, water does not gradually make more steam the more it's heated. It will start off not making any steam, and then once it reaches a certain point, steam starts. This means something can stay still for years (such as a communist party not making any progress), and then suddenly make progress (such as the communist party suddenly seeing a surge in new members as the contradictions of capitalism worsen).

All change has a quantitative aspect, that is, an aspect of mere increase or decrease which does not alter the nature of that which changes. But quantitative change, increase or decrease, cannot go on indefinitely. At a certain point it always leads to a qualitative change; and at that critical point, the qualitative change takes place relatively suddenly.

A classical example of this is water. If water is being heated, it does not go on getting hotter and hotter indefinitely; at a certain critical temperature, it begins to turn into steam, undergoing a qualitative change from liquid to gas. Another example is a rope used to lift a weight, which may have a greater and greater load attached to it, but no rope can lift a load indefinitely great: at a certain point, the rope is bound to break. We can measure the weight attached to the rope as a quantity, a number, and the qualitative change is the fact that the rope broke. It was whole, now it's broken. Dialectical change has happened to it.

There is a very important component to take into account here, and that is the rule of autodynamism. Change in dialectics comes from internal forces; if change has happened through external forces, then it is not dialectics. For example if you put an apple into the juicer, then the solid apple has transformed into a liquid. While that is change, it is not internal change: you have applied mechanical force to the apple. Dialectical change to the apple would be it following its normal course of life: budding, flowering, becoming a fruit, ripening, falling from the tree, and rotting.

Unity and struggle of opposites[edit | edit source]

Everything exists only in relation to an opposite or contrary thing. The two opposites are therefore united by the interdependence on the existence of the other, yet also struggle against each other. This is also known as a contradiction.

As Mao explained in On Contradiction, there is a contradiction when two things are fundamentally opposed, but one cannot exist without the other. In this case a thing can be anything: ideas, concepts, commodities, fields of science, tangible items...

Examples include the contradiction between theory and praxis. Theory can only exist in relation to practice with the real world (praxis), and praxis cannot exist without practicing theory. Theory without practice leads to metaphysics and unreliable ideas; praxis without theory leads to vulgar empiricism and ineffective action and therefore, theory and praxis are in contradiction as they struggle to adjust to reflect each other.

Negation of the negation[edit | edit source]

When a contradiction is resolved, it is negated. But this negation makes a new contradiction emerge, which will itself be negated eventually in order to be solved. Contradiction 1 -> Contradiction 2 -> Contradiction 3. To get from 1 to 3, contradiction 2 needs to happen. Thus the negation (which is contradiction 2) is negated (by contradiction 3).

Since a contradiction needs two components to exist and creates a third component when it's resolved, that third component will find its own contradiction, i.e. its diametrical opponent. For example, a seed contains within it the contradiction to become a plant: it has the potential to bloom, but does not currently exist as a plant while it exists in seed form. When the contradiction is resolved, the seed starts to sprout. This creates a (young) plant, which is the negation to the seed. The negation to the sprout is the mature plant that starts to bear flowers: the negation of the negation.

The plant cannot exist without the seed, and the seed can't exist without at least the potential to become a plant (otherwise it wouldn't be a seed). This makes it a contradiction.

Distinction from dualism[edit | edit source]

Dialectical materialism is distinct from dualism. Dualism frames the world as a pair of mutually negating forces -- that of idea and matter, consciousness and being -- and that correspondingly, phenomena also fall into two categories: the ideal and the material, which negate each other, and contend against each other, so that the development of nature and society is a constant struggle between ideal and material phenomena. Dialectical materialism views these opposed forces as distinct parts of the whole substance. Like the two sides of a coin.[6]

Examples[edit | edit source]

An apple[edit | edit source]

An apple is not set in stone. It will not remain an apple forever. Before being an apple, the fruit was a flower, and before that a bud on a branch. As we can see, change has happened to the apple and will continue to happen. The apple will ripen, and later will fall off the tree and then start rotting, feeding more life. The process goes on forever even if, at some point, anyone looking at the apple will say "this isn't an apple anymore, it's just mush". The apple itself has stopped existing, but it was just one stage of an ongoing process and the process itself still exists. Incidentally, this is what metaphysical materialists don't understand. They will study the apple as it is an apple, not seeing the whole process. One branch of science will study the apple, and another will study the flower that later becomes the apple.[7]

Class struggle[edit | edit source]

There is a very apparent contradiction in the class struggle. The bourgeoisie is fundamentally opposed to the proletariat -- as the former wants to extract more value from their employees, while the latter wants to retain more value from their employer. Yet one class cannot exist without the other: if the bourgeoisie did not have the proletariat to exploit, then they would change into another class over time. For a concrete example, we can look at the end of feudalism. The Bourgeoisie revolted against the old regime of the nobles and feudal masters and eventually took power (such as in France). Before that point, the bourgeoisie existed side-by-side with the nobles and both competed for the supremacy of their class (as in class society, there is always an exploiting class and exploitative class). Yet the proletariat did not exist side-by-side with the serves. There were free cities, in which guilds operated and they employed workers by the day or week, but this is different from the proletariat (as seen in Principles of Communism). It was only after the feudal order was abolished, with the bourgeoisie taking over the state, that the proletariat developed itself. Thus the contradiction mutated, and the class struggle moved from the nobles and serves to the bourgeoisie and proletariat.

To exemplify another rule of dialectics, we also see that quantitative change leads to qualitative change. Essentially, as more people became either bourgeoisie or manufacture workers (the ancestor of the proletariat), their numbers grew -- quantitative change. When their numbers grew enough and it was impossible for them to develop as a class any longer, and they had a chance of seizing state power, they did -- and if it was successful, then this quantitative change led to qualitative change.

Misconceptions[edit | edit source]

Dialectics only apply to political science[edit | edit source]

Some people believe that dialectics and dialectical materialism only apply to political science, or even more specifically to Marxism alone and are just one way of seeing the world out of many competing but equally valid frameworks.

Dialectical materialism is the most advanced way to study and understand the world as of yet because it follows scientific principles, is derived from natural phenomena, and simply is the most able framework to explain the objective nature of the world (in terms of correct analyses and predictions). It is not specifically Marxist either and can be used by anyone. Dialectical materialism is a framework to study the world, and works as a "base" to build upon.

Dialectics, because they exist in the world, apply to everything that surrounds us and are not limited to any field of science or domain of use. Dialectics happen in every material phenomena, "material" meaning anything that exists in the material world. Since we know only the material world exists (the one we live in), everything that exists is by definition material and logically subject to dialectics.

Dialectics are too difficult to understand and not needed to organize[edit | edit source]

There is an effort in bourgeois academia to make philosophy remain the language of a few elites. Words can be daunting at first glance, and the effort is spent to keep these words vague, difficult to understand, mystical, and requiring years of study to even grasp their meaning.

Philosophy can be and is proletarian, it shouldn't belong solely to the bourgeoisie. It is not necessary to read Hegel to understand dialectics: what matters is understanding dialectics, and after that reading Hegel if one wishes. This requires revolutionaries to work towards demystifying philosophy and teach it in a proletarian manner, so that all workers may understand it. It was for this reason that when teaching philosophy, Politzer didn't spend time walking the student through all idealist philosophers and their differences: he started directly at Berkeley, who had theorized idealism in its most advanced form. When teaching dialectics, he used everyday examples of material phenomena that all of us have observed.

Dialectics form the basis to an objective understanding of the world, which includes class society and the class struggle. Without the proper application of dialectics to analyze one's current material conditions in society, it is impossible to apply praxis effectively.

See also[edit | edit source]

Further Reading[edit | edit source]

Elementary principles of philosophy by Georges Politzer

References[edit | edit source]

  1. “Dialectics, so-called objective dialectics, prevails throughout nature, and so-called subjective dialectics, dialectical thought, is only the reflection of the motion through opposites which asserts itself everywhere in nature, and which by the continual conflict of the opposites and their final passage into one another, or into higher forms, determines the life of nature.”

    Friedrich Engels (1883). Dialectics of nature: 'Notes and fragments; Dialectics'.
  2. “But Marx did not stop at eighteenth-century materialism: he developed philosophy to a higher level, he enriched it with the achievements of German classical philosophy, especially of Hegel's system, which in its turn had led to the materialism of Feuerbach. The main achievement was dialectics, i.e., the doctrine of development in its fullest, deepest and most comprehensive form, the doctrine of the relativity of the human knowledge that provides use with a reflection of eternally developing matter. The latest discoveries of natural science—radium, electrons, the transmutation of elements—have been a remarkable confirmation of Marx's dialectical materialism despite the teachings of the bourgeois philosophers with their "new" reversions to old and decadent idealism.”

    Vladimir Lenin (1913). The three sources and three component parts of Marxism.
  3. “My dialectic method is not only different from the Hegelian, but is its direct opposite. To Hegel, the life process of the human brain, i.e., the process of thinking, which, under the name of “the Idea,” he even transforms into an independent subject, is the demiurgos of the real world, and the real world is only the external, phenomenal form of “the Idea.” With me, on the contrary, the ideal is nothing else than the material world reflected by the human mind, and translated into forms of thought.

    The mystifying side of Hegelian dialectic I criticised nearly thirty years ago, at a time when it was still the fashion. [...] The mystification which dialectic suffers in Hegel’s hands, by no means prevents him from being the first to present its general form of working in a comprehensive and conscious manner. With him it is standing on its head. It must be turned right side up again, if you would discover the rational kernel within the mystical shell.”

    Karl Marx (1873). Afterword to the second German edition of Capital, vol. I.
  4. V. Adoratsky. Dialectical materialism - the theoretical foundation of Marxism-Leninism, pg. 22-23
  5. Humphrey McQueen (year of publication unknown). from Hegel's Logic to Lenin's Imperialism and beyond. [PDF]
  6. Joseph Stalin (1907). Anarchism Or Socialism?: 'Chapter II The Materialist Theory'. Moscow: Foreign Languages Publishing House. [MIA]
  7. Georges Politzer (1946). Elementary principles of philosophy. International Publishers.